qui
parle


A journal of critical
humanities and
social sciences,
since 1985.

Recent
Archive
Contributors
About
Submit
Contact
︎Ki

CfP: Form and its Discontents





Copyright © 2024 Editorial Board, Qui Parle
Qui Parle, Volume 10, Number 2, Spring/Summer 1997

Vol. 10 | No. 2 | Spring/Summer 1997


    Special Issue: Heidegger & Co.

Philosophy, Metaphysics, Democracy
Gianni Vattimo
Translated by Paul Kottman

In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:

We confront the problem of the relationship between philosophy and politics at a moment which, at least in my opinion, is characterized by two "epochal" events with all the risks which the use of that term entails. On the one hand, philosophy has lived through, and is still living through, that process which Heidegger called the "end of metaphysics": namely, the dissolution of the pretenses' of foundational thought, the so-called "crisis of reason"––which, although perhaps over-emphasized or reduced to a generic slogan, is a fact that is difficult to ignore. On the other hand, on the side of politics, the fall of real socialism has cast a pall of discredit over ideological politics of a "deductive" or global kind, leaving behind a largely "Popperian" liberalism, which endeavors to think the political pragmatically in terms of small steps, or trial and error. Even if there is no causal connection between the one and the other, these two events are obviously connected. Already before the fall of real socialism, the crisis of metaphysics (in the Heideggerian sense) had also developed in connection with the waning of the political conditions for a universalistic thought: for instance, the end of colonialism, the emerging voice of other cultures and the parallel emergence of cultural anthropology, or the discrediting of the myth of a unilinear progress of humanity, guided by the most civilized West. (This crisis, too, was "practical" before it was "theoretical"; witness the first world war.)

Read now at JSTOR


Jean-Luc Nancy, Myth, and Literature
Jed Deppman

In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:

Jean-Luc Nancy stands out among recent theorists of community for his willingness to use myth and literature as important analytical categories. One of his more striking and fundamental theses is that even though literature does not have an identifiable essence, somehow in the way that it "interrupts" myth it reproduces the truth of community, the very truth of how we are together.

Readers of Nancy know that such a claim can be understood in several ways: as a thesis on the ontology of literariness, a phenomenological description of the act of reading, a postmodern (anti)constitutive theory of community, even (were it drawn out) a negative statement about the possibility of effective political activity in the time of late capitalism. These and other possibilities are usually in play when Nancy invokes myth and literature, and this multivalence is one reason that he has attracted more attention from political than from literary theorists. Another obvious reason is that his use of literature always seems to some extent opportunistic––more the consequence of his proximity to Derrida and post-structuralism than the result of any real engagement with literary texts.

Read now at JSTOR


Il faut
Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe
Translated by Jeff Fort

In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:

"To write, the exigency to write": the formulation is from Maurice Blanchot. What is at stake in it, and one can hear this right away, is the very essentiality of what we no longer have the nerve to name "literature." Without making a stir, almost modestly, but in a way that is altogether decisive. By means of this imperative without content, what was known as "literature"––a term which has authorized so many immense pretentions and inspired poses––is given over to its own naked existence as a fact and to a sort of duty without reason, much as the Rimbaud of A Season in Hell claimed to be given over to the earth and to a crude reality. In a register which, despite appearances, is quite close to this, when Beckett was asked by a newspaper survey the question "Why do you write?", he gave this lapidary response: "It's all I'm good for" [Bon qu'à ça].

In order to say this exigency, we have in our language––that is, in this French which Hölderlin spoke a little and with which, in any case, he punctuated his late sketches and the last reworkings of his greatest poems––we have a formidable locution: "it is necessary" [il faut]. Formidable but, undoubtedly, irreplaceable.

Read now at JSTOR


Superseding Deconstruction: Blanchot, Hegel, and the Theory of Epochs
Raj Sampath

In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:

Traces of Hegel's metaphysics and shadows of his teleology of history haunt much poststructuralist thought. Hegel's ghost lingers in such works as Michel Foucault's Madness and Civilization (1961) and The Order of Things (1966), Gilles Deleuze's Difference and Repetition (1968) and The Logic of Sense (1969), Jacques Lacan's The Four Fundamental Concepts of Psychoanalysis (1964) and Écrits (1966), Jacques Derrida's Edmund Husserl's Origin of Geometry: An Introduction (1961) and Of Grammatology (1967), Michel Serres's The System of Leibniz (1968), and Jean Baudrillard's Consumer Society (1970). This is a strange and controversial proposition. For these thinkers––among others––were responsible for a series of powerful critiques; under explicit attack, were the humanist, metaphysical, and teleological foundations of the human sciences of the nineteenth and twentieth-centuries. In short, these thinkers dismantled some of the deepest presuppositions that underpin the "Philosophy of History." Thus how can one possibly substantiate a correlation between the critiques made by contemporary French thought and Hegel's 'metaphysics'? No doubt, 'poststructuralism' has left an indelible mark on our contemporary theoretical imagination and its opaque temporal horizon. But this mark also conceals a deep anxiety over Hegelianism and its legacy. For poststructuralism not only affects our attitudes on the 'historical present' but the question of how one temporalizes the historicity––or ‘historical finitude’––of any philosophy of history (Hegelian or otherwise).

Read now at JSTOR


Vocation and Voice
Giorgio Agamben
Translated by Jeff Fort

In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:

The title of my paper attempts, with its etymological figure, to think in another language a German term that appears in certain decisive passages of Hölderlin and Heidegger. This term is the substantive Stimmung. If it is true that we can think only by way of language, if, as Wittgenstein put it, every philosophical interrogation can be presented as an interrogation of the meaning of words, then translation is one of the eminent means by which man thinks his words.

Now, as a great philologist once remarked, the German word Stimmung is precisely one of those words that we tend to define as untranslatable. "This does not mean," this same philologist adds, "that phrases such as 'in guter Stimmung sein' could not easily be rendered by 'to be in a good mood' or by the French 'être en bonne humeur'; 'die Stimmung in diesem Zimmer' by 'the atmosphere in this room'; 'Stimmung hervorrufen' by 'to create an atmosphere'; 'die Seele zu Traurigkeit stimmen' by 'to dispose the soul to sadness', etc. But what is missing in the main European languages is a term that would express the unity of the feelings experienced by man face to face with his environment (a landscape, nature, one's fellow man), and would comprehend and weld together the objective (factual) and the subjective (psychological) into one harmonious unity...

Read now at JSTOR


   Review Essay

Safranski's Heidegger: Notes on the Philosophical Ramifications of Biography
Peter Eli Gordon

A review of Safranski, Rüdiger. Martin Heidegger: Between Good and Evil. Translated from the German by Ewald Osers. (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998).

Read now at JSTOR



Volume 10.2 is available at JSTOR. Qui Parle is edited by an independent group of graduate students at the University of California, Berkeley and published by Duke University Press.